![]() |
中文首页 | 研究团队 | 中心简介 | 实验经济学FAQ | 重要链接 |
![]() |
经典文献 |
V. Smith, (1994). "Economics in the Laboratory," Journal of Economic Perspectives
8(1), 113-131. By Why do economists conduct experiments? To answer
that question, it is first necessary briefly to specify the ingredients of an
experiment. Every laboratory experiment is defined by an environment,
specifying the initial endowments, preferences and costs that motivate
exchange. This environment is controlled using monetary rewards to induce the
desired specific value/cost configuration (Smith, 1991, 6).1 An experiment also
uses an institution defining the language (messages) of market communication
(bids, offers, acceptances), the rules that govern the exchange of information,
and the rules under which messages become binding contracts. This institution
is defined by the experimental instructions which describe the messages and
procedures of the market, which are most often computer controlled. Finally,
there is the observed behavior of the participants in the experiments as a
function of the environment and institution that constitute the controlled
variables. V. Smith, (1987) V. Smith, (1982). "Microeconomic Systems as an Experimental Science,"
American Economic Review
72(5), 923-955.atwell, Murray Milgate, and Peter Newman, reproduced with
permission of Palgrave. By Historically, the method and subject matter of
economics have presupposed that it was a non-experimental (or 'field
observational') science more like astronomy or meteorology than physics or
chemistry. Based on general, introspectively 'plausible', assumptions about
human preferences, and about the cost and technology based supply response of
producers, economists have sought to understand the functioning of economies,
using observations generated by economic outcomes realized over time. The data
of the astronomer is of this same type, but it would be wrong to conclude that
astronomy and economics are methodologically equivalent. There are two
important differences between astronomy and economics which help to illuminate
some of the methodological problems of economics. First, based upon parallelism
(maintained hypotheisis that the same physical laws hold everywhere), astronomy
draws on all the relevant theory from classical mechanics and particle physics
-- theory which has evolved under rigorous laboratory tests. Traditionally,
economists have not had an analogous body of tested behavioural principles that
have survived controlled experimental tests, and which can be assumed to apply
with insignificant error to the microeconomic behaviour that underpins the
observable operations of the economy. Analogously, one might have supposed that
there would have arisen an important area of common interest between economics
and, say, experimental psychology, similar to that between astronomy and
physics, but this has only started to develop in recent years. V. Smith, (1982). "Microeconomic Systems as an Experimental Science,"
American Economic Review
72(5), 923-955. By The experimental literature contains only a few
attempts to articulate a "theory" of laboratory experiments in
economics (Charles Plott, 1979; Louis Wilde, 1980; my articles, Daniel Kahneman
and Amos Tversky(1979). "Prospect Theory: An Analysis of Decision under Risk", Econometrica, Vol. 47, No. 2, (Mar.,
1979), pp. 263-291 By Daniel Kahneman This paper presents a critique of expected utility
theory as a descriptive model of decision making under risk, and develops an
alternative model, called prospect theory. Choices among risky prospects
exhibit several pervasive effects that are inconsistent with the basic tenets
of utility theory. In particular, people underweight outcomes that are merely
probable in comparison with outcomes that are obtained with certainty. This
tendency, called the certainty effect, contributes to risk aversion in choices
involving sure gains and to risk seeking in choices involving sure losses. In
addition, people generally discard components that are shared by all prospects
under consideration. This tendency, called the isolation effect, leads to
inconsistent preferences when the same choice is presented in different forms.
An alternative theory of choice is developed, in which value is assigned to
gains and losses rather than to final assets and in which probabilities are
replaced by decision weights. The value function is normally concave for gains,
commonly convex for losses, and is generally steeper for losses than for gains.
Decision weights are generally lower than the corresponding probabilities,
except in the range of low prob-abilities. Overweighting of low probabilities
may contribute to the attractiveness of both insurance and gambling. Amos
Tversky, Paul Slovic, Daniel Kahneman(1990). “The Causes of Preference
Reversal”, The American Economic Review,
Vol. 80, No. 1, (Mar., 1990), pp. 204-217 By Daniel Kahneman Observed
preference reversal (PR) cannot be adequately explained by violations of
independence, the reduction axiom, or transitivity. The primary cause of PR is
the failure of procedure invariance, especially the overpricing of
low-probability high-payoff bets. This result violates regret theory and
generalized (nonindepen-dent) utility models. PR and a new reversal involving
time preferences are explained by scale compatibility, which implies that
payoffs are weighted more heavily in pricing than in choice. |